- UID
- 3066
- 在线时间
- 小时
- 注册时间
- 2003-4-27
- 最后登录
- 1970-1-1
- 主题
- 帖子
- 性别
- 保密
|
6#
楼主 |
发表于 2003-6-9 13:53:00
|
只看该作者
第五课,非常重要。非看不可! Premises, Conclusions, and Support
An argument is a series of statements used to persuade someone of something. That "something" is called the conclusion or main claim. The first job in analyzing any argument is to identify its conclusion. One way to identify conclusions, or other parts of an argument, is to look for their indicators.: The language in which an argument is presented often contains words or phrase to help identify its parts, especially its premises and conclusion. These words and phrases are identifiers of the function played in the argument. Unfortunately, identifiers are only as precise as the persons using them, and both the individual making an argument and the one evaluating it are liable to make mistakes by inexact or sloppy use of identifiers. Since the purpose of an argument is to communicate an idea clearly, the careful use and interpretation of identifiers is an important skill for critical thinking.
The following are some of the most common premise and conclusion identifiers:
Premise identifiers: Conclusion identifiers: since therefore for thus because so supposing that as a result given that consequently assuming that we can conclude that
These are only a few of the words and phrases commonly used to identify premises and conclusions. In addition, keep in mind that:
some of these words can also appear within the context of an argument, but without indicating an inference. "So," for example, has several meanings, only one of which is a synonym for "therefore." sloppy usage may produce confusing identifiers. A common answer to the question, "What would you think if the sky suddenly clouded up and turned very dark," is "I would assume it was going to rain." Yet "it is going to rain" here is a conclusion, not an assumption or premise. "if" and "then" are often used to identify premises and conclusions, respectively. However, "if" and "then" are also used to introduce the two halves of a conditional premise. In either usage, "then" is sometimes omitted; and it has other meanings, as well. an identifier may not immediately precede or follow the word or phrase whose function it is indicating. For example, in the sentence "Thus, whenever the sun rises, the rooster crows," there are two claims: a premise, "the sun rises," and a conclusion identified by "thus" (but not immediately following it), "the rooster crows." in cases where there are no identifiers, the most frequent order is conclusion first, followed by one or both premises. If both premises are given, they are often conjoined with "and" or "but." For example, "I like Mozart. I like most classical composers, and Mozart was a classical composer."
Premises are statements that directly support the conclusion. A simple argument has two premises and a conclusion; a more complex argument may contain many claims, but these can always be divided up into groups of three--two premises and a conclusion. In an argument, the conclusion is only supported by its two premises, but each premise itself can be supported in a number of ways:
Supporting arguments. A supporting argument is one which has as its conclusion the same statement as the premise being supported. All premises can be supported in this way, but such supporting arguments are often not stated. A special type of supporting argument is a definition, and while these, too, are usually unstated, at times it is necessary to define a term because either the term itself or the particular denotation being used is unusual. Assumptions. Eventually, all support for premises can be traced back to a set of beliefs which the person making the argument considers to be self-evident, and therefore not in need of further support or analysis. These may be called assumptions, presumptions, suppositions, or, in certain situations, postulates and axioms. Such assumptions serve as the premises for supporting arguments and, in general, any premise can be called an assumption. Evidence. A premise can be made more acceptable when it supported by various kinds of evidence: statistical studies, historical information, physical evidence, observations, or experiments, eyewitness accounts, and so on. The relative strength of evidence is determined by how reliable a person believes it to be. Almost no evidence is beyond dispute--we might challenge the methodology of a study, the accuracy of the information, the manner in which physical evidence was collected, and the eyesight or motivation of an eyewitness. And remember that the evidence only supports the premises--evidence cannot be an argument itself. Authority. Sometimes, we are not in a position to judge supporting evidence for ourselves: there may simply be too much of it, or it may be too technical in nature, or it may not be directly available to us. In those cases we often rely on the judgments of others, authorities whom we believe to be more likely to come to an accurate evaluation of the evidence than we are ourselves. Though we tend to think of such expertise in scientific, medical, or other scholarly fields, authority in arguments can also come from religious teachings, folk wisdom, and popular sayings--anything or anyone that we accept as somehow able to reach a more accurate evaluation. The relative strength of an authority in an argument depends on how willing a person is to accept the judgment of that source, but even in the strongest of cases, use of an authority merely supports a premise, and does not make an argument by itself. Explanations and anecdotes. Sometimes, we are more willing to accept a premise if we are given background information or specific examples. Such explanations and accounts are not given the importance of evidence or authority in an argument. Anecdotal evidence, for example, is by definition less statistically reliable than other sorts of evidence, and explanations do not carry the weight of authority. But both anecdotal evidence and explanations may affect our understanding of a premise, and therefore influence our judgment. The relative strength of an explanation or an anecdote is usually a function of its clarity and applicability to the premise it is supporting. The various sorts of support for a premise--supporting arguments, evidence, authority, and explanations and anecdotes--interact in what we might call a hierarchy of support or evidence, in which one sort is given priority over another. In a murder trial, for example, the prosecution is usually based on the assumption that the jury's hierarchy of evidence will have at the top physical evidence (fingerprints, blood samples), especially as explained by technical authorities (forensic pathologists, ballistics experts), followed by eyewitness accounts, then by other sorts of authorities (psychologists, sociologists), and finally by explanations and anecdotes (character witnesses, personal histories). If the prosecution is right, their strong physical evidence and eyewitness accounts will outweigh the defendant's character witnesses, because of their relative placement in the jury's hierarchy of evidence. However, because that hierarchy is determined by each individual on a case-by-case basis, one can never be totally sure how any one piece of support will be accepted.
Facts and Opinions. In the section on statements, we distinguish between three kinds of claims: verifiable, evaluative, and advocatory. Generally speaking, evidence takes the form of a verifiable statement, and authority takes the form of a evaluative statement. We have avoided using the terms "fact" and "opinion," in part because of the strong connotations these words carry. People tend to think that "facts" are much more reliable and convincing than "opinions," yet many "facts," such as statistical surveys, scientific measurements, and historical events, are ultimately based on "opinions." Thus, the difference between verifiable evidence ("The victim's blood was found on the suspect's clothes") and evaluative authority ("According to my analysis, the sample taken from the suspect's clothes matches the victim's blood type), is often more a matter of presentation than of fact vs. opinion.
今天的内容就这么多。原来每刻都有一些练习,可是都有链接,不好粘。等我以后总结出来了再粘吧。内容比较多,看起来很累。我也看得很累。慢慢来。这前面是基础。后面的东东才难。实在不行大家全当练写作argument作文好了。我给大家看看整个结构: The Basics
Parts of an Argument Statements Statements and Conversions Universal Statements Vagueness and Ambiguity Premises, Conclusions, and Support Inference Identifiers Exercises for Identifiers Validity, Truth, and Soundness Basic Relations Conjunctions and Disjunctions Exercises for Conjunctions and Disjunctions Options Exercises for Options Analysis of Arguments
Introduction to Inductive and Deductive Reasoning Inductive Arguments Causal Arguments Exercises for Causal Arguments Deductive Arguments Exercises for Deductive Arguments Conditional Arguments Exercises for Conditional Arguments "Only" in Conditional Arguments Exercises for "Only" Conditionals Conditional Chain Arguments Exit Quiz for Conditionals Universal Syllogisms Exercises for Universal Syllogisms Non-Universal Syllogisms Exercises for Non-Universal Syllogisms Exit Quiz for Syllogisms 60 Deductive Review Exercises Fallacies and Non-Rational Persuasion
Fallacious Appeals Misdirected Appeals: Appeal to Authority Appeal to Common Belief Common Practice Two Wrongs Indirect Consequences Wishful Thinking
Emotional Appeals: Appeal to Fear Appeal to Loyalty Appeal to Pity Appeal to Prejudice Appeal to Spite Appeal to Vanity
Exercises for Fallacious Appeals Generalizations Ad Hominem Attacks Exercises for Ad Hominem Attacks Other Common Fallacies Post Hoc Reasoning Straw Man Burden of Proof Circular Reasoning Loaded Question False Dilemma Unfair Fallacies: False Compromise False Equity
Exit Quiz for Fallacies 40 Fallacy Review Exercises
很吓人,不过要使大家掌握了这些东西,用美国人的逻辑思维加上一定的阅读能力,逻辑拿高分肯定没有问题。我的目标是争取错一个以内。我们一起努力!!
[此贴子已经被作者于2003-6-9 14:04:31编辑过] |
|